• [ Pobierz caÅ‚ość w formacie PDF ]

    offer balm for the spirit, but it is not a religious balm. Exactly what sort of
    balm is it? Therein lies a tale . . .
    Aesthetic Judgment and Beauty
     Tantalizing is not a word most people associate with the work of Immanuel
    Kant. But the first half of his Critique of Judgement, which deals with the nature
    of aesthetic judgment, is full of tantalizing observations about the nature of
    THE VOCATION OF ART 181
    aesthetic experience. Kant saw that the appeal of aesthetic experience was
    strikingly different from the appeal of sensory pleasure, on the one hand,
    and the satisfaction we take in the good, moral, or practical, on the other.
    For one thing, with both sensory pleasure and the good, our satisfac-
    tion is inextricably bound up with interest, which is to say with the exist-
    ence of whatever it is that is causing the pleasure. When we are hungry, a
    virtual dinner will not do: we want the meat and potatoes. It is the same
    with the good: a virtual morality is not moral.
    Things are different with aesthetic pleasure. There is something pecu-
    liarly disengaged about aesthetic pleasure. When it comes to our moral and
    sensory life, we are constantly reminded that we are creatures of lack: we
    are hungry and wish to eat, we see the good and know that we fall short.
    But when we judge something to be beautiful, Kant says, the pleasure we
    take in that judgment is ideally an  entirely disinterested satisfaction. 3
    The great oddity about aesthetic judgment is that it provides satisfaction
    without the penalty exacted by desire. This accounts both for its power and
    for its limitation. The power comes from the feeling of wholeness and
    integrity that a disinterested satisfaction involves. Pleasure without desire is
    pleasure unburdened by lack. The limitation comes from the fact that, unbur-
    dened by lack, aesthetic pleasure is also unmoored from reality. Precisely
    because it is disinterested, there is something deeply subjective about aes-
    thetic pleasure: what we enjoy is not an object but our state of mind. Kant
    spoke in this context of  the free play of the imagination and the under-
    standing  it is  free because it is unconstrained by interest or desire.4
    It is a curious fact that in his reflections on the nature of aesthetic judg-
    ment Kant is only incidentally interested in art. The examples of  pure
    beauty he provides are notoriously trivial: sea shells, wallpaper, musical
    fantasies, architectural ornamentation. But Kant was not attempting to pro-
    vide lessons in art appreciation. He was attempting to explain the mechan-
    ics of taste. It is not surprising that the Critique of Judgement became an
    important theoretical document for those interested in abstract art: in Kant s
    view, the purest beauty was also the most formal, the most abstract.
    There is, however, another side to Kant s discussion of beauty. This has
    to do with the moral dimension of aesthetic judgment. If the pleasure we
    take in the beautiful is subjective, Kant argued, it is nonetheless not sub-
    jective in the same way that sensory pleasure is subjective. You like your
    182 RELIGION AND THE AMERICAN FUTURE
    steak well done, I like mine rare: that is a mere subjective preference. But
    when it comes to the beautiful, Kant observes, we expect broad agreement.
    And this is because we have faith that the operation of taste that  free play
    of the imagination and understanding  provides a common ground of
    judgment. We cannot prove that a given object is beautiful, because the point
    at issue is not the object but the state of mind it occasions. Nevertheless,
    Kant says,  We woo the agreement of everyone else, because we have for it
    a ground that is common to all. 5 Which is to say that if judgments about
    the beautiful are in one sense subjective, in another sense they are universal
    because they exhibit our common humanity. The feeling of freedom and
    wholeness that aesthetic experience imparts is thus not merely private but
    reminds us of our vocation as moral beings. In this context, Kant famously
    spoke of beauty as being  the symbol of morality because in aesthetic pleas-
    ure  the mind is made conscious of a certain ennoblement and elevation. 6
    Art without Beauty
    But wait a moment:  Ennoblement ?  Elevation ? What are we talking about
    here? It is worth pausing to consider the tremendous irony that attends our
    culture s continuing investment in art emotional, financial, and social
    investment given the oppositional and  transgressive character of much of
    the contemporary art world. We continue to behave as if art were something
    special, something important, something spiritually refreshing. But when we
    canvas the roster of  name artists today, what do we find?
    Well, doubtless we find a great many things. But it is striking how much
    of what we find exists in the febrile bubble of  cutting-edge notoriety. It is
    a curious situation. Traditionally, the goal or end of fine art was to make
    beautiful objects. Beauty itself came with a lot of Platonic and Christian
    metaphysical baggage, some of it indifferent or even, nota bene, positively
    hostile to art. But art without beauty was, if not exactly a contradiction in
    terms, at least a description of failed art. How different things are today!
    But if large precincts of the art world have jettisoned the traditional link
    between art and beauty, they have done nothing to disown the social pre-
    rogatives of art. Indeed, we suffer today from a peculiar form of moral anes-
    thesia: an anesthesia based on the delusion that by calling something  art
    THE VOCATION OF ART 183
    we thereby purchase for it a blanket exemption from moral criticism as if
    being art automatically rendered all moral considerations beside the point.
    George Orwell gave classic expression to this point in  Benefit of Clergy:
    Some Notes on Salvador Dalí. Acknowledging the deficiency of the philis-
    tine response to Dalí s work categorical rejection along with denial that
    Dalí possessed any talent whatever Orwell goes on to note that the
    response of the cultural elites was just as impoverished. Essentially, the elite
    response to Dalí was the response of l art pour l art, of extreme aestheticism.
     The artist, Orwell writes,
    is to be exempt from the moral laws that are binding on ordinary
    people. Just pronounce the magic word  Art, and everything is
    O.K. Rotting corpses with snails crawling over them are O.K.;
    kicking little girls in the head is O.K.; even a film like L Age d Or
    [which shows among other things detailed shots of a woman
    defecating] is O.K.7
    A juror in the obscenity trial in Cincinnati over Robert Mapplethorpe s
    notorious photographs of the S&M homosexual underworld memorably
    summed up the paralyzed attitude Orwell described. Acknowledging that
    he did not like Mapplethorpe s rebarbative photographs, the juror nonethe-
    less concluded that  if people say it s art, then I have to go along with it. 8
     If people say it s art, then I have to go along with it. It is worth paus-
    ing to digest that comment. It is also worth confronting it with a question:
    Why do so many people feel that if something is regarded as art, they  have
    to go along with it, no matter how offensive it might be? Part of the answer [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]

  • zanotowane.pl
  • doc.pisz.pl
  • pdf.pisz.pl
  • zambezia2013.opx.pl